About
this issue
The two key focuses of this issue of IPG are Designing policies for development and
Threats and war scenarios. Further to this,
Jürgen Kahl analyses
the significance of China joining the WTO and Carlos
Santiso looks at the problems and prospects of international
promotion of democracy.
There is no doubt that the essay by Carlos Santiso is particularly significant
for a journal published by the Friedrich Ebert Foundation.
Santiso debates the project which lies at the heart
of the international activities of the German political
foundations: promoting democracy in developing countries
and countries in transition. It is true that Santiso
only touches on the German foundations,
and that only in the singular, concealing the limits
to his knowledge behind the remark that the work of
the foundations has been insufficiently analyzed. However,
Santiso's analysis and criticism of the official support
policies does shed light indirectly on the work of the foundations,
which he implicitly supports.
As Santiso criticizes, the official policies adhere
to a template. Democracy is established in a three-pronged
process: elections plus the formation of democratic
institutions plus support for civil society. However,
the use of "democracy templates" cannot meet
the needs of the diverse and unpredictable realities
in the developing countries and countries in transition;
this standardized approach cannot overcome the current
stagnation in democratization to be seen from Belarus
to Paraguay. However, the "template" does
have one implicit advantage, and Santiso's essay itself
bears witness to this: it can be criticized, differentiated
and further developed strategically.
The work of the German foundations is anything
but template-based. This can be seen simply from the
fact that six political foundations operate with different
priorities. The international work of the foundations
also tends to be more path-based than strategic. It
is not based on a master plan. It is true that the foundations
would interpret the totality of their international
activities as direct or indirect contributions towards
democratization, but they would scarcely subsume them
under the general heading "promoting democracy",
since they pursue parallel objectives (representation
of social interests, economic development, adult education,
promotion of women in society, etc.) to an equal extent.
And their concept of democracy is more broadly based,
i.e. it is not restricted to the political institutions
in the narrower sense (plus civil society). The work
is more varied, and so the foundations are more capable
of responding flexibly to different and fluctuating
conditions. These advantages go hand in hand with a
disadvantage, the opposite one from that of the official
model: despite (or because of) their flexibility, they
find it more difficult to cope with systematically organized
learning processes.
The experience underpinning the article by Carlos
Santiso is the US promotion of democracy, which differs
from the approach of the German foundations in several
ways. A first difference refers to the relationship
between political parties and civil society. The
promotion of organizations of civil society plays an
important role in both US and German practice. But the
great importance attached to civil society in the American
case derives from a fundamental pessimism about the
state. The necessary distrust of the executive, particularly
in countries which have just opted for democracy, is
turned into a sort of general liberal suspicion of the
state. This pessimism about the state can become a danger
if, as in many developing countries and countries in
transition, the problem lies not in excessive state
power, but in inadequate state development. The only
alternative to state failure is the state itself, as
Santiso aptly quotes. If it promotes an apparently autonomous
subpolitics or antipolitics of “society”, the promotion
of democracy threatens to undermine the legitimacy of
democratically elected governments. The foundations,
in contrast, draw a fuzzier distinction between civil
society and the state. The political parties, which
are placed at the interface between civil society and
the state, are not separated off from civil society
and categorized within the narrowly defined sphere of
politics, but are viewed as organizations open to civil
society. At the same time, the limits of organizations
of civil society are respected. These lie not only in
a lack of democratic legitimacy on the input side, but
also in their structural incompetence on the output
side: before movements in civil society are transformed
into legitimate state action, they need to pass through
a whole range of barriers, with the political parties
providing the reservoir of professional gatekeepers.
A second
difference to which Santiso refers is the concept
of pluralism,
which underpins the promotion of democracy. The US organizations
and the German foundations will certainly agree that
democracy forms the political framework for a pluralistic
competition of values and interests. However, in the
American concept, the installation of this framework
stands ahead of and above this competition, and this
leads to the restraint on promoting political parties
which Santiso observes. The German foundations, in contrast,
are already "party-based" due to the way they
are organized, i.e. they are inclined towards specific
political orientations. They are not merely convinced
of the idea of democratic pluralism: they represent
it. To simplify: the US approach is concentrated on
the design of the forms
in which democratic decision-making processes can
take place, without wishing to influence the outcome
of this process; the approach taken by the foundations,
in contrast, is focused on the content
– on material policy options and their sponsors.
Thirdly, in this context, there is a difference in the understanding of society's
interests.
The US approach basically sees only two really relevant
interest groups: the advocates and opponents of democracy.
The central line of conflict is between a society viewed
as genuinely democratic and a state which always tends
to be exposed to the temptations of autocracy. Opposing
economic and social interests are blocked out. However,
it is precisely these which are at the heart of the
work of the foundations. The promotion of democracy
is also understood to mean the empowerment of individuals
and social groups to represent their interests publicly,
effectively and non-violently. Democracy does not overcome
opposing social interests, but makes it possible to
manage the conflict in a "political process"
in a form in which the political framework is not repeatedly
questioned.
Obviously, these differences should not be exaggerated.
They should be viewed as different emphases which mutually
complement each other. In practice, the promotion of
democracy is a joint project of US and German organizations
which is often managed in co-operation. However, a more
precise mutual and self-observation could make it easier
for each side to reflect on the assumptions underlying
its own work. For the American approach to promoting
democracy, the varied approaches and experiences of
German foundations could act as a stimulus to make the
US activities more flexible; for the German foundations,
the US approach of systematic self-reflection – and
the contribution by Carlos Santiso stands for an entire
branch of literature here – could help them to subject
their own activities to a more intensive self-reflection.
Michael
Ehrke